skip to main |
skip to sidebar
Is Eating a Cinnamon Roll Irrational? (A Review Of Phishing for Phools: The Economics of Manipulation and Deception)
By Tyler Kubik of Mises Daily.
"The literature on market imperfection and market failure is
voluminous, ever-growing, and filled with Nobel laureates. Identify a
new source or instance of market “failure,” and you’re likely to win a
Nobel Prize, or so it seems.
Phishing for Phools: The Economics of Manipulation and Deception,
by Nobel Laureates George A. Akerlof and Robert J. Shiller, presents
the thesis that we are overly confident in unregulated markets and that
entrepreneurs accrue profit by preying on hapless consumers, exploiting
“our weakness in knowing what we really want” through the market’s
tendency “to spawn manipulation and deception.” Mavens of manipulation
themselves, Akerlof and Shiller claim many, if not most people —
especially the poor — are irrationally exuberant and are induced into
buying things they really do not want. How do they know what the
consumer really wants, one might ask? The answer is that anything the
authors would not do themselves is ipso facto not in the best interest of the consumer. In fact, it is something that “no one could possibly want.”
We’ll Decide What’s Best For You
Their
opening chapter is an exercise in convoluted methodology. In it,
Akerlof and Shiller obliterate any distinction between adroit
entrepreneurship/marketing and deception/fraud. The most fundamental
problem, however, is that Akerlof and Shiller think that what people
really want is what is (objectively) good for them. They refuse to
recognize that even if consumers were aware of the costs of eating
Cinnabon — their bĂȘte noire in the opening chapter — and consuming a high calorie meal devoid of nutrients, they still might choose to eat Cinnabon.
In their paternalist fervor, they cannot fathom that some people, in
some places, at some times, might be willing to make such a trade off.
Rejecting Mises’s economic tautology that business owners stay afloat by satisfying consumer preferences
through voluntary exchange, they believe that, instead, business owners
compete for who can best deceive their customers. They call Cinnabon’s
efforts to attract customers by making their product more desirable and
available in convenient locations “phishing.”
Is the alternative, then, to mandate that businesses instead locate their stores in inconvenient
locations, where they are less likely to sell their products to
increase market efficiency? No answer is forthcoming. Also never
answered by the duo is, if advertising is so effective at deceiving
consumers, why do firms not spend nearly all of their budgets on
advertising? Wildly exaggerating the problem they present, Akerlof and
Shiller even think that the cumulative effect of “phishing” that
companies like Cinnabon do through luring people in with the aroma of
their cinnamon rolls may be as significant as the financial crash of
2008.
“Information Asymmetry” or Just Division of Labor?
They
also maintain that the incompetence of the average person prevents them
from wisely investing their funds. What they do not show is that a
disinterested bureaucrat spending someone else’s money has an
incentive to invest carefully, which they simply assume. No matter that
an individual has knowledge of his time, place, and preferences that a
bureaucrat cannot have, regardless of whether or not consumers make
systematic cognitive errors. What they call informational asymmetries,
i.e., the different levels of knowledge among consumers and producers, should properly be called the division of labor and knowledge in society,
which underpins all markets and gives us a basis to make exchanges in
the first place. It is for the very reason, namely that producers of
goods know more about the goods they produce, that we purchase from
them. Hence, in criticizing information asymmetry in markets, they are
criticizing all exchange. Akerlof and Shiller habitually succumb to this
Nirvana fallacy,
holding up the utopian ideal of perfect information as their
(unreachable) model, and then when markets fail to reach this ideal,
assume that this justifies government intervention, never giving us a
reason why these systemic cognitive biases and information asymmetries
can be avoided by bureaucrats more than they can by the average
consumer.
Variety and Convenience Are Bad Things?
Fundamentally,
they mistake the beauty of the market and its convenience with
manipulation. When they see a wide variety of products to choose from
within arm’s reach, such as in a supermarket, they view it as a scheme
to induce consumerist depravity and indulgence, rather than as a wonder
to behold. They critique overpaying for health plans at the same time
they critique obesity. We also see them succumbing to extraordinarily
misleading explanations of history. For instance, in chapter six, they
repeated the canard that Upton Sinclair’s The Jungle exposed the meatpacking industry’s unsanitary practices, when in fact his book was a complete fabrication, making no mention of this.
In
general, Akerlof and Shiller appear oblivious to the roles consumer
reporting institutions, competition, reputation, repeated dealings, and
quality assurance play in doing just what they claim markets fail to do.
If they desired to write a complete, and balanced look at the
phenomenon they studied, rather than forward their agenda — what is in
reality a jobs program for economists — they had ample material with
which to work. The “heroes” of the story, instead, are primarily
government regulators, and others who “step back from the profit
incentive.” The profit incentive, for them, is essentially a one-way
trip down Deceit Drive toward Manipulation Station. This single chapter
focuses on the ways these problems are overcome, but they present
nothing but impotency regarding the ability of businesses to do anything
other than manipulate and deceive. The market, apparently, cannot
provide solutions to or protect against this predatory behavior they
attribute to these businesses, evidence to the contrary notwithstanding.
We are left with the impression that these phishing problems are real,
devastating, pervasive, and unresolved, as well as the impression that
the solution is government regulation and bureaucratic administration.
Nothing could be further from the truth.
In every instance,
Akerlof and Shiller showcase their own “irrational exuberance” and
monomania for decrying consumer choices, rather than market failures
arising from information asymmetries. What else can we conclude from the
foregoing but that there are informational asymmetries abounding about
the true value of the information in Phishing for Phools — and
that it is, objectively, something that “No One Could Possibly Want” to
buy? If there is anything that could shake one’s faith in unregulated
markets, it’s that anyone could be duped by Phishing for Phools."
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.